Nominative
Accusative
Dative
Ablative
Genitive
Vocative
Locative
Passive
Deponent
Institutio Oratoria (Quintilian)
Rainbow Latin Reader
[Close]
 

Institutio Oratoria

Author: Quintilian
Translator: Harold Edgeworth Butler
1407
Omnis
igitur
probatio
artificialis
constat
aut
signis
aut
argumentis
aut
exemplis
.
Nec
ignoro
plerisque
videri
signa
partem
argumentorum
.
Quae
mihi
separandi
ratio
haec
fuit
prima
,
quod
sunt
paene
ex
illis
inartificialibus
;
cruenta
enim
vestis
et
clamor
et
livor
et
talia
sunt
instrumenta
,
qualia
tabulae
,
rumores
,
testes
;
nec
inveniuntur
ab
oratore
,
sed
ad
eum
cum
ipsa
causa
deferuntur
;
Every artificial proof consists either of indications, arguments or examples. I am well aware that many consider indications to form part of the arguments. My reasons for distinguishing them are twofold. In the first place indications as a rule come under the head of inartificial proofs: for a bloodstained garment, a shriek, a dark blotch and the like are all evidence analogous to documentary or oral evidence and rumours; they are not discovered by the orator, but are given him with the case itself.
1408
altera
,
quod
signa
,
sive
indubitata
sunt
,
non
sunt
argumenta
,
quia
,
ubi
ilia
sunt
,
quaestio
non
est
,
argumento
autem
nisi
in
re
controversa
locus
esse
non
potest
;
sive
dubia
,
non
sunt
argumenta
sed
ipsa
argumentis
egent
.
My second reason was that indications, if indubitable, are not arguments, since they leave no room for question, while arguments are only possible in controversial matters. If on the other hand they are doubtful, they are not arguments, but require arguments to support them.
1409
Dividuntur
autem
in
has
duas
primas
species
,
quod
eorum
alia
sunt
,
ut
dixi
,
quae
necessaria
sunt
,
alia
quae
non
necessaria
.
Priora
illa
sunt
quae
aliter
habere
se
non
possunt
,
quae
Graeci
vocant
τεκμήρια
,
quia
sunt
ἄλυτα
σημεῖα
,
quae
mihi
vix
pertinere
ad
praecepta
artis
videntur
;
nam
ubi
est
signum
insolubile
,
ibi
ne
lis
quidem
est
.
The two first species into which artificial proofs may be divided are, as I have already said, those which involve a conclusion and those which do not. The former are those which cannot be otherwise and are called τεκμήρια, by the Greeks, because they are indications from which there is no getting away. These however seem to me scarcely to come under the rules of art. For where an indication is irrefutable, there can be no dispute as to facts.
1410
Id
autem
accidit
,
cum
quid
aut
necesse
est
fieri
factumve
esse
aut
omnino
non
potest
fieri
vel
esse
factum
;
quo
in
causis
posito
non
est
lis
facti
.
Hoc
genus
per
omnia
tempora
perpendi
solet
.
This happens whenever there can be no doubt that something is being or has been done, or when it is impossible for it to be or have been done. In such cases there can be no dispute as to the fact. This kind of proof may be considered in connexion with past, present or future time.
1411
Nam
et
coisse
eam
cum
viro
,
quae
peperit
,
quod
est
praeteriti
,
et
fluctus
esse
,
cum
magna
vis
venti
in
mare
incubuit
,
quod
coniuncti
,
et
eum
mori
,
cuius
cor
est
vulneratum
,
quod
futuri
,
necesse
est
.
Nec
fieri
potest
,
ut
ibi
messis
sit
,
ubi
satum
non
est
,
ut
quis
Romae
sit
,
cum
est
Athenis
,
ut
sit
ferro
vulneratus
,
qui
sine
cicatrice
est
.
For example, a woman who is delivered of a child must have had intercourse with a man, and the reference is to the past. When there is a high wind at sea, there must be waves, and the reference is to the present. When a man has received a wound in the heart, he is bound to die, and the reference is to the future. Nor again can there be a harvest where no seed has been sown, nor can a man be at Rome when he is at Athens, nor have been wounded by a sword when he has no scar. Some have the same force when reversed:
1412
Sed
quaedam
et
retrorsum
idem
valent
,
ut
vivere
hominem
qui
spirat
,
et
spirare
qui
vivit
.
Quaedam
in
contrarium
non
recurrent
;
nec
enim
,
quia
movetur
qui
ingreditur
,
etiam
ingreditur
qui
movetur
.
a man who breathes is alive, and a man who is alive breathes. Some again cannot be reversed: because he who walks moves it does not follow that he who moves walks.
1413
Quare
potest
et
coisse
cum
viro
,
quae
non
peperit
,
et
non
esse
ventus
in
mari
,
cum
est
fluctus
,
neque
utique
cor
eius
vulneratum
esse
,
qui
perit
.
Ac
similiter
satum
fuisse
potest
,
ubi
non
fuit
messis
,
nec
fuisse
Romae
,
qui
non
fuit
Athenis
,
nec
fuisse
ferro
vulneratus
,
qui
habet
cicatricem
.
So too a woman, who has not been delivered of a child, may have had intercourse with a man, there may be waves without a high wind, and a man may die without having received a wound in the heart. Similarly seed may be sown without a harvest resulting, a man, who was never at Athens, may never have been at Rome, and a man who has a scar may not have received a sword-wound.
1414
Alia
sunt
signa
non
necessaria
,
quae
εἰκότα
Graeci
vocant
;
quae
etiamsi
ad
tollendam
dubitationem
sola
non
sufficiunt
,
tamen
adiuncta
ceteris
plurimum
valent
.
There are other indications or εἰκότα, that is probabilities, as the Greeks call them, which do not involve a necessary conclusion. These may not be sufficient in themselves to remove doubt, but may yet be of the greatest value when taken in conjunction with other indications.
1415
Signum
vocatur
,
ut
dixi
,
σημεῖον
quamquam
id
quidam
indicium
quidam
vestigium
nominaverunt
,
per
quod
alia
res
intellegitur
,
ut
per
sanguinem
caedes
.
At
sanguis
vel
ex
hostia
respersisse
uestem
potest
vel
e
naribus
profluxisse
:
non
utique
,
qui
vestem
cruentam
habuerit
,
homicidium
fecerit
.
The Latin equivalent of the Greek σημεῖον is signum, a sign, though some have called it indicium, an indication, or vestigium, a trace. Such signs or indications enable us to infer that something else has happened; blood for instance may lead us to infer that a murder has taken place. But bloodstains on a garment may be the result of the slaying of a victim at a sacrifice or of bleeding at the nose. Everyone who has a bloodstain on his clothes is not necessarily a murderer.
1416
Sed
ut
per
se
non
sufficit
,
ita
ceteris
adiunctum
testimonii
loco
ducitur
,
si
inimicus
,
si
minatus
ante
,
si
eodem
in
loco
fuit
;
quibus
signum
cum
accessit
,
efficit
ut
,
quae
suspecta
erant
,
certa
videantur
.
But although such an indication may not amount to proof in itself, yet it may be produced as evidence in conjunction with other indications, such for instance as the fact that the man with the bloodstain was the enemy of the murdered man, had threatened him previously or was in the same place with him. Add the indication in question to these, and what was previously only a suspicion may become a certainty.
1417
Alioqui
sunt
quaedam
signa
utrique
parti
communia
,
ut
livores
,
tumores
(
nam
videri
possunt
et
veneficii
et
cruditatis
)
et
vulnus
in
pectore
sua
manu
et
aliena
perisse
dicentibus
,
in
quo
est
.
Haec
proinde
firma
habentur
atque
extrinsecus
adiuvantur
.
On the other hand there are indications which may be made to serve either party, such as livid spots, swellings which may be regarded as symptoms either of poisoning or of bad health, or a wound in the breast which may be treated as a proof of murder or of suicide. The force of such indications depends on the amount of extraneous support which they receive.
1418
Eorum
autem
,
quae
signa
sunt
quidem
,
sed
non
necessaria
,
genus
Hermagoras
putat
,
non
esse
virginem
Atalantam
,
quia
cum
iuvenibus
per
silvas
vagetur
.
Quod
si
receperimus
,
vereor
,
ne
omnia
quae
ex
facto
ducuntur
signa
faciamus
.
Eadem
tamen
ratione
qua
signa
tractantur
.
Hermagoras would include among such indications as do not involve a necessary conclusion, an argument such as the following, " Atalanta cannot be a virgin, as she has been roaming the woods in the company of young men. " If we accept this view, I fear that we shall come to treat all inferences from a fact as indications. None the less such arguments are in practice treated exactly as if they were indications.
1419
Nec
mihi
videntur
Areopagitae
,
cum
damnaverint
puerum
coturnicum
oculos
eruentem
,
aliud
iudicasse
quam
id
signum
esse
perniciosissimae
mentis
multisque
malo
futurae
,
si
adolevisset
.
Unde
Spurii
Maelii
Marcique
Manlii
popularitas
signum
adfectati
regni
est
existimatum
.
Nor do the Areopagites, when they condemned a boy for plucking out the eyes of quails, seem to have had anything else in their mind than the consideration that such conduct was an indication of a perverted character which might prove hurtful to many, if he had been allowed to grow up. So, too, the popularity of Spurius Maelius and Marcus Manlius was regarded as an indication that they were aiming at supreme power.
1420
Sed
vereor
,
ne
longe
nimium
nos
ducat
haec
via
.
Nam
si
est
signum
adulterae
lavari
cum
viris
,
erit
et
convivere
cum
adolescentibus
,
deinde
etiam
familiariter
alicuius
amicitia
uti
;
fortasse
corpus
vulsum
,
fractum
incessum
,
vestem
muliebrem
dixerit
mollis
et
parum
viri
signa
,
si
cui
(
cum
signum
id
proprie
sit
,
quod
ex
eo
,
de
quo
quaeritur
,
natum
sub
oculos
venit
)
ut
sanguis
e
caede
,
ita
illa
ex
impudicitia
fluere
videantur
.
However, I fear that this line of reasoning will carry us too far. For if it is an indication of adultery that a woman bathes with men, the fact that she revels with young men or even an intimate friendship will also be indications of the same offence. Again depilation, a voluptuous gait, or womanish attire may be regarded as indications of effeminacy and unmanliness by anyone who thinks that such symptoms are the result of an immoral character, just as blood is the result of a wound: for anything, that springs from the matter under investigation and comes to our notice, may properly be called an indication.
1421
Ea
quoque
quae
,
quia
plerumque
observata
sunt
,
vulgo
signa
creduntur
,
ut
prognostica
.
Vento
rubet
aurea
Phoebe
et
Cornix
plena
pluviam
vocat
improba
voce
,
si
causas
ex
qualitate
caeli
trahunt
,
sane
ita
appellentur
.
Similarly it is also usual to give the names of signs to frequently observed phenomena, such as prognostics of the weather which we may illustrate by the Vergilian
"For wind turns Phoebe's face to ruddy gold"
and
"The crow
With full voice, good-for-naught, invites the rain."
If these phenomena are caused by the state of the atmosphere, such an appellation is correct enough.
1422
Nam
si
vento
rubet
luna
,
signum
venti
est
rubor
.
Et
si
,
ut
idem
poeta
colligit
,
densatus
et
laxatus
aer
facit
,
ut
sit
inde
ille
avium
concentus
,
idem
sentiemus
.
Sunt
autem
signa
etiam
parva
magnorum
,
ut
vel
haec
ipsa
cornix
;
nam
maiora
minorum
esse
,
nemo
miratur
.
For if tile moon turns red owing to the wind, her hue is certainly a sign of wind. And if, as the same poet infers, the condensation and rarification of the atmosphere causes that "concert of bird-voices" of which he speaks, we may agree in regarding it as a sign. We may further note that great things are sometimes indicated by trivial signs, witness the Vergilian crow; that trivial events should be indicated by signs of greater importance is of course no matter for wonder.
1423
Nunc
de
argumentis
.
Hoc
enim
nomine
complectimur
omnia
,
quae
Graeci
ἐνθυμήματα
,
ἐπιχειρήματα
,
ἀποδείξεις
,
vocant
,
quanquam
apud
illos
est
aliqua
horum
nominum
differentia
,
etiamsi
vis
eodem
fere
tendit
.
Nam
enthymema
(
quod
nos
commentum
sane
aut
commentationem
interpretemur
,
quia
aliter
non
possumus
,
Graeco
melius
usuri
)
unum
intellectum
habet
,
quo
omnia
mente
concepta
significat
(
sed
nunc
non
de
eo
loquimur
) ;
alterum
,
quo
sententiam
cum
ratione
;
I now turn to arguments, the name under which we comprise the ἐνθυμήματα, ἐπιχειρήματα, and ἀποδείξεις of the Greeks, terms which, in spite of their difference, have much the same meaning. For the enthymeme (which we translate by commentun or commentatio, there being no alternative, though we should be wiser to use the Greek name) has three meanings: firstly it means anything conceived in the mind (this is not however the sense of which I am now speaking);
1424
tertium
,
quo
certam
quandam
argumenti
conclusionem
vel
ex
consequentibus
vel
ex
repugnantibus
,
quanquam
de
hoc
parum
convenit
.
Sunt
enim
,
qui
illud
prius
epichirema
dicant
,
pluresque
invenias
in
ea
opinione
,
ut
id
demum
,
quod
pugna
constat
,
enthymema
accipi
velint
,
et
ideo
illud
Cornificius
contrarium
appellat
.
secondly it signifies a proposition with a reason, and thirdly a conclusion of an argument drawn either from denial of consequents or from incompatibles ; although there is some controversy on this point. For there are some who style a conclusion from consequents an epicheireme, while it will be found that the majority hold the view that an epicheireme is a conclusion from incompatibles: wherefore Cornificius styles it a contrarium or argument from contraries. Some again call it a rhetorical
1425
Hunc
alii
rhetoricum
syllogismum
,
alii
imperfectum
syllogismum
vocaverunt
,
quia
nec
distinctis
nec
totidem
partibus
concluderetur
;
quod
sane
non
utique
ab
oratore
desideratur
.
syllogism, others an incomplete syllogism, because its parts are not so clearly defined or of the same number as those of the regular syllogism, since such precision is not specially required by the orator. Valgius translates ἐπιχείρημα by aggressio,
1426
Epichirema
Valgius
aggressionem
vocat
;
verius
autem
iudico
,
non
nostram
administrationem
sed
ipsam
rem
quam
aggredimur
,
id
est
argumentum
,
quo
aliquid
probaturi
sumus
,
etiamsi
nondum
verbis
explanatum
,
iam
tamen
mente
conceptum
,
epichirema
dici
.
that is an attempt. It would however, in my opinion, be truer to say that it is not our handling of the subject, but the thing itself which we attempt which should be called an ἐπιχείρημα, that is to say the argument by which we try to prove something and which, even if it has not yet been stated in so many words, has been clearly conceived by the mind.
1427
Aliis
videtur
non
destinata
vel
inchoata
,
sed
perfecta
probatio
hoc
nomen
accipere
,
ultima
specie
;
ideoque
propria
eius
appellatio
et
maxime
in
usu
est
posita
,
qua
significatur
certa
quaedam
sententiae
comprehensio
,
quae
ex
tribus
minimum
partibus
constat
.
Others regard it not as an attempted or imperfect proof, but a complete proof, falling under the most special species of proof; consequently, according to its proper and most generally received appellation it must be understood in the sense of a definite conception of some thought consisting of at least three parts. Some call an ἐπιχείρημα a reason,
1428
Quidam
epichirema
rationem
appellarunt
,
Cicero
melius
ratiocinationem
,
quanquam
et
ille
nomen
hoc
duxisse
magis
a
syllogismo
videtur
.
Nam
et
statum
syllogisticum
ratiocinativum
appellat
,
exemplisque
utitur
philosophorum
.
Et
quoniam
est
quaedam
inter
syllogismum
et
epichirema
vicinitas
,
potest
videri
hoc
nomine
recte
abusus
.
but Cicero is more correct in calling it a reasoning, although he too seems to derive this name from the syllogism rather than anything else; for he calls the syllogistic basis a ratiocinative basis and quotes philosophers to support him. And since there is a certain kinship between a syllogism and an epicheireme, it may be thought that he was justified in his use of the latter term.
1429
Ἀπόδειξις
est
evidens
probatio
,
ideoque
apud
Geometras
γραμμικαὶ
ἀποδείξεις
dicuntur
Hanc
et
ab
epichiremate
Caecilius
putat
differre
solo
genere
conclusionis
et
esse
apodixin
imperfectum
epichirema
eadem
causa
,
qua
diximus
enthymema
syllogismo
distare
.
Nam
et
epichirema
syllogismi
pars
est
.
Quidam
inesse
epichiremati
apodixin
putant
et
esse
partem
eius
confirmantem
.
An ἀπόδεξις is a clear proof; hence the use of the term γραμμικαὶ ἀποδείξεις, "linear demonstrations" by the geometricians. Caecilius holds that it differs from the epicheireme solely in the kind of conclusion arrived at and that an apodeixis is simply an incomplete epicheireme for the same reason that we said an enthymeme differed from a syllogism. For an epicheireme is also part of a syllogism. Some think that an apodeixis is portion of an epicheireme, namely the part containing the proof.
1430
Utrumque
autem
quanquam
diversi
auctores
eodem
modo
finiunt
,
ut
sit
ratio
per
ea
,
quae
certa
sunt
,
fidem
dubiis
adferens
;
quae
natura
est
omnium
argumentorum
,
neque
enim
certa
incertis
declarantur
.
Haec
omnia
generaliter
πίστεις
appellant
,
quod
etiamsi
propria
interpretatione
dicere
fidem
possumus
,
apertius
tamen
probationem
interpretabimur
.
Sed
argumentum
quoque
plura
significat
.
But all authorities, however much they may differ on other points, define both in the same way, in so far as they call both a method of proving what is not certain by means of what is certain. Indeed this is the nature of all arguments, for what is certain cannot be proved by what is uncertain. To all these forms of argument the Greeks give the name of πίστεις , a term which, though the literal translation is fides "a warrant of credibility," is best translated by probatio "proof." But argument has several other meanings.
1431
Nam
et
fabulae
ad
actum
scenarum
compositae
argumenta
dicuntur
,
et
orationum
Ciceronis
velut
thema
ipse
exponens
Pedianus
,
Argumentum
,
inquit
,
tale
est
;
et
ipse
Cicero
ad
Brutum
ita
scribit
:
ueritus
fortasse
,
ne
nos
in
Catonem
nostrum
transferremus
illinc
aliquid
,
etsi
argumentum
simile
non
erat
.
Quo
apparet
omnem
ad
scribendum
destinatam
materiam
ita
appellari
.
For the plots of plays composed for acting in the theatre are called arguments, while Pedianus, when explaining the themes of the speeches of Cicero, says The argument is as follows. Cicero himself in writing to Brutus says, Fearing that I might transfer something from that source to my Cato, although the argument is quite different. It is thus clear that all subjects for writing are so called.
1432
Nec
mirum
,
cum
id
inter
opifices
quoque
vulgatum
sit
,
unde
Vergilius
,
Argumentum
ingens
;
vulgoque
paulo
numerosius
opus
dicitur
argumentosum
.
Sed
nunc
de
eo
dicendum
argumento
est
,
quod
probationem
praestat
.
Celsus
quidem
probationem
,
indicium
,
fidem
,
adgressionem
eiusdem
rei
nomina
facit
,
parum
distincte
,
ut
arbitror
.
Nor is this to be wondered at, since the term is also in common use among artists; hence the Vergilian phrase A mighty argument. Again a work which deals with a number of different themes is called "rich in argument." But the sense with which we are now concerned is that which provides proof Celsus indeed treats the terms, proof, indication, credibility, attempt, simply as different names for the same things, in which, to my thinking, he betrays a certain confusion of thought.
1433
Nam
probatio
et
fides
efficitur
non
tantum
per
haec
quae
sunt
rationis
,
sed
etiam
per
inartificialia
.
Signum
autem
,
quod
ille
indicium
vocat
,
ab
argumentis
iam
separavi
.
Ergo
,
cum
sit
argumentum
ratio
probationem
praestans
,
qua
colligitur
aliud
per
aliud
,
et
quae
quod
est
dubium
per
id
quod
dubium
non
est
confirmat
,
necesse
est
esse
aliquid
in
causa
,
quod
probatione
non
egeat
.
For proof and credibility are not merely the result of logical processes, but may equally be secured by inartificial arguments. Now I have already distinguished signs or, as he prefers to call them, indications from arguments. Consequently, since an argument is a process of reasoning which provides proof and enables one thing to be inferred from another and confirms facts which are uncertain by reference to facts which are certain, there must needs be something in every case which requires no proof.
1434
Alioqui
nihil
erit
quo
probemus
,
nisi
fuerit
quod
aut
sit
verum
aut
videatur
,
ex
quo
dubiis
fides
fiat
.
Pro
certis
autem
habemus
primum
,
quae
sensibus
percipiuntur
,
ut
quae
uidemus
,
audimus
,
qualia
sunt
signa
;
deinde
ea
,
in
quae
communi
opinione
consensum
est
,
deos
esse
,
Otherwise there will be nothing by which we can prove anything; there must be something which either is or is believed to be true, by means of which doubtful things may be rendered credible. We may regard as certainties, first, those things which we perceive by the senses, things for instance that we hear or see, such as signs or indications; secondly, those things about which there is general agreement, such as the existence of the gods or the duty of loving one's parents;
1435
praestandam
pietatem
parentibus
;
praeterea
,
quae
legibus
cauta
sunt
,
quae
persuasione
etiamsi
non
omnium
hominum
,
eius
tamen
civitatis
aut
gentis
,
in
qua
res
agitur
,
in
mores
recepta
sunt
,
ut
pleraque
in
iure
non
legibus
sed
moribus
constant
;
si
quid
inter
utramque
partem
convenit
,
si
quid
probatum
est
,
denique
cuicunque
adversarius
non
contradicit
.
Sic
enim
fiet
argumentum
,
thirdly, those things which are established by law or have passed into current usage, if not throughout the whole world, at any rate in the nation or state where the case is being pleaded—there are for instance many rights which rest not on law, but on custom; finally, there are the things which are admitted by either party, and whatever has already been proved or is not disputed by our adversary.
1436
Cum
providentia
mundus
regatur
,
administranda
respublica
est
;
sequitur
ut
administranda
respublica
sit
,
si
liquebit
mundum
prouidentia
regi
.
Thus for instance it may be argued that since the world is governed by providence, the state should similarly be governed by some controlling power: it follows that the state must be so governed, once it is clear that the world is governed by providence.
1437
Debet
etiam
nota
esse
recte
argumenta
tractaturo
vis
et
natura
omnium
rerum
,
et
quid
quaeque
earum
plerumque
efficiat
;
hinc
enim
sunt
,
quae
εἰκότα
dicuntur
.
Further, the man who is to handle arguments correctly must know the nature and meaning of everything and their usual effects. For it is thus that we arrive at probable arguments or εἰκότα as the Greeks call them.
1438
Credibilium
autem
genera
sunt
tria
:
unum
firmissimum
,
quia
fere
accidit
,
ut
liberos
a
parentibus
amari
;
alterum
velut
propensius
,
eum
qui
recte
valeat
in
crastinum
perventurum
;
tertium
tantum
non
repugnans
,
in
domo
furtum
factum
ab
eo
qui
domi
fuit
.
With regard to credibility there are three degrees. First, the highest, based on what usually happens, as for instance the assumption that children are loved by their parents. Secondly, there is the highly probable, as for instance the assumption that a man in the enjoyment of good health will probably live till to-morrow. The third degree is found where there is nothing absolutely against an assumption, such as that a theft committed in a house was the work of one of the household.
1439
Ideoque
Aristoteles
in
secundo
de
Arte
Rhetorica
libro
diligentissime
est
exsecutus
,
quid
cuique
rei
et
quid
cuique
homini
soleret
accidere
,
et
quas
res
quosque
homines
quibus
rebus
aut
hominibus
vel
conciliasset
vel
alienasset
ipsa
natura
:
ut
divitias
quid
sequatur
aut
ambitum
aut
superstitionem
,
quid
boni
probent
,
quid
mali
petant
,
quid
milites
,
quid
rustici
,
quo
quaeque
modo
res
vitari
vel
appeti
soleat
.
Verum
hoc
exsequi
mitto
;
Consequently Aristotle in the second book of his Rhetoric has made a careful examination of all that commonly happens to things and persons, and what things and persons are naturally adverse or friendly to other things or persons, as for instance, what is the natural result of wealth or ambition or superstition, what meets with the approval of good men, what is the object of a soldier's or a farmer's desires, and by what means everything is sought or shunned.
1440
non
enim
longum
tantum
,
sed
etiam
impossibile
aut
potius
infinitum
est
,
praeterea
positum
in
communi
omnium
intellectu
.
Si
quis
tamen
desideraverit
,
a
quo
peteret
,
ostendi
.
Omnia
autem
credibilia
,
For my part I do not propose to pursue this subject. It is not merely a long, but an impossible or rather an infinite task; moreover it is within the compass of the common understanding of mankind. If, however, anyone wishes to pursue the subject, I have indicated where he may apply.
1441
in
quibus
pars
maxima
consistit
argumentationis
,
ex
huiusmodi
fontibus
fluunt
:
an
credibile
sit
a
filio
patrem
occisum
,
incestum
cum
filia
commissum
;
et
contra
,
veneficium
in
noverca
,
adulterium
in
luxurioso
;
illa
quoque
,
an
scelus
palam
factum
,
an
falsum
propter
exiguam
summam
,
quia
suos
quidque
horum
velut
mores
habet
,
plerumque
tamen
,
non
semper
;
alioqui
indubitata
essent
,
non
argumenta
.
But all credibility, and it is with credibility that the great majority of arguments are concerned, turns on questions such as the following: whether it is credible that a father has been killed by his son, or that a father has committed incest with his daughter, or to take questions of an opposite character, whether it is credible that a stepmother has poisoned her stepchild, or that a man of luxurious life has committed adultery; or again whether a crime has been openly committed, or false evidence given for a small bribe, since each of these crimes is the result of a special cast of character as a rule, though not always; if it were always so, there would be no room for doubt, and no argument.
1442
Excutiamus
nunc
argumentorum
locos
;
quanquam
quibusdam
hi
quoque
,
de
quibus
supra
dixi
,
videntur
.
Locos
appello
non
,
ut
vulgo
nunc
intelliguntur
,
in
luxuriam
et
adulterium
et
similia
;
sed
sedes
argumentorum
,
in
quibus
latent
,
ex
quibus
sunt
petenda
.
Nam
,
Let us now turn to consider the "places" of arguments, although some hold that they are identical with the topics which I have already discussed above. But I do not use this term in its usual acceptance, namely, commonplaces directed against luxury, adultery, and the like, but in the sense of the secret places where arguments reside, and from which they must be drawn forth.
1443
ut
in
terra
non
omni
generantur
omnia
,
nec
avem
aut
feram
reperias
,
ubi
quaeque
nasci
aut
morari
soleat
ignarus
,
et
piscium
quoque
genera
alia
planis
gaudent
alia
saxosis
,
regionibus
etiam
litoribusque
discreta
sunt
,
nec
helopem
nostro
mari
aut
scarum
ducas
,
ita
non
omne
argumentum
undique
venit
ideoque
non
passim
quaerendum
est
.
For just as all kinds of produce are not provided by every country, and as you will not succeed in finding a particular bird or beast, if you are ignorant of the localities where it has its usual haunts or birthplace, as even the various kinds of fish flourish in different surroundings, some preferring a smooth and others a rocky bottom, and are found on different shores and in divers regions (you will for instance never catch a sturgeon or wrasse in Italian waters), so not every kind of argument can be derived from every circumstance, and consequently our search requires discrimination.
1444
Multus
alioqui
error
est
;
exhausto
labore
,
quod
non
ratione
scrutabimur
,
non
poterimus
invenire
nisi
casu
.
At
si
scierimus
,
ubi
quodque
nascatur
,
cum
ad
locum
ventum
erit
,
facile
quod
in
eo
est
pervidebimus
.
Otherwise we shall fall into serious error, and after wasting our labour through lack of method we shall fail to discover the argument which we desire, unless assisted by some happy chance. But if we know the circumstances which give rise to each kind of argument, we shall easily see, when we come to a particular "place," what arguments it contains.