Nominative
Accusative
Dative
Ablative
Genitive
Vocative
Locative
Passive
Deponent
Institutio Oratoria (Quintilian)
Rainbow Latin Reader
[Close]
 

Institutio Oratoria

Author: Quintilian
Translator: Harold Edgeworth Butler
875
Alii
sex
status
putant
,
coniecturam
,
quam
γένεσιν
vocant
,
et
qualitatem
,
et
proprietatem
,
id
est
μετάστασις
quo
verbo
finitio
ostenditur
,
et
quantitatem
,
quam
μετάστασις
;
dicunt
,
et
comparationem
,
et
translationem
,
cuius
adhuc
novum
nomen
inventum
est
μετάστασις
novum
,
inquam
,
in
statu
,
alioqui
ab
Hermagora
inter
species
iuridiciales
usitatum
.
Others hold that there are six bases: conjecture or γένεσις, quality, particularity or ἰδιότης by which word they mean definition, quantity or ἀξία, comparison and competence, for which a new term has been found in μετάστασις I call it new when applied to a basis, for Hermagoras employs it to describe a species of juridical question.
876
Aliis
septem
esse
placuit
;
a
quibus
nec
translatio
nec
quantitas
nec
comparatio
recepta
est
,
sed
in
horum
trium
locum
subditae
quattuor
legales
adiectaeque
tribus
illis
rationalibus
.
Others think there are seven, while refusing to recognise competence, quantity or comparison, in place of which they substitute four legal bases, completing the seven by the addition of those three which they call rational.
877
Alii
pervenerunt
usque
ad
octo
,
translatione
ad
septem
superiores
adiecta
.
A
quibusdam
deinde
divisa
ratio
est
,
ut
status
rationales
appellarent
,
quaestiones
(
quemadmodum
supra
dixi
)
legales
,
ut
in
illis
de
re
,
in
his
de
scripto
quaereretur
.
Quidam
in
diversum
hos
status
esse
,
Others again make eight by the addition of competence to the above-mentioned seven. Some on the other hand have introduced a fresh method of division, reserving the name of bases for the rational, and giving the name of questions to the legal, as I mentioned above, since in the former the problem is concerned with facts, in the latter with the letter of the law. Some on the contrary reverse this nomenclature calling the legal questions bases and the rational grounds questions.
878
illas
quaestiones
maluerunt
.
Sed
alii
rationales
tres
putaverunt
,
An
sit
?
Quid
sit
?
Quale
sit
?
Hermagoras
solus
quattuor
,
coniecturam
,
proprietatem
,
translationem
,
qualitatem
,
quam
per
accidentia
,
id
est
κατὰ
συμβεβηκός
vocat
,
hac
interpretatione
,
an
illi
accidat
viro
bono
esse
,
vel
malo
.
Hanc
ita
dividit
,
de
appetendis
et
fugiendis
,
quae
est
pars
deliberativa
;
But others have thought that there are only three rational bases, covered by the questions whether a thing is, what it is, and of what kind it is? Hermagoras is alone in thinking that there are four, namely conjecture, particularity, competence, and quality: to the latter he appends the phrase κατὰ συμβεβηκός "according to its accidents," illustrating his meaning by putting a case where it is enquired whether a man happen to be good or bad. He then subdivides quality into four species: first that which is concerned with things to he sought or avoided, which belongs to deliberative oratory:
879
de
persona
,
ea
ostenditur
laudativa
;
negotialem
,
quam
πραγματικήν
vocat
,
in
qua
de
rebus
ipsis
quaeritur
,
remoto
personarum
complexu
,
ut
,
Sitne
liber
qui
est
in
assertione
,
an
divitiae
superbiam
pariant
,
an
iustum
quid
,
an
bonum
sit
.
Iuridicialem
,
in
qua
fere
eadem
sed
certis
destinatisque
personis
quaerantur
:
an
ille
iuste
hoc
fecerit
,
vel
bene
secondly those concerned with persons, by which he indicates panegyric: thirdly the practical or pragmatic, which is concerned with things in general without reference to persons, and may be illustrated by questions such as whether he is free who is claimed as a slave and waiting the trial of his case, whether riches beget insolence, and whether a thing is just or good; lastly there is the juridical species, under which practically the same questions arise, but in relation to certain definite persons, as for instance when it is asked whether that particular man has done well or ill.
880
Nec
me
fallit
,
in
primo
Ciceronis
rhetorico
aliam
esse
loci
negotialis
interpretationem
,
cum
ita
scriptum
sit
:
Negotialis
est
,
in
qua
,
quid
iris
ex
civili
more
et
aequitate
sit
,
consideratur
;
cui
diligentiae
praeesse
apud
nos
iurisconsulti
existimantur
.
I am aware that another explanation is given by Cicero in the first book of his Rhetorica of the species known as practical, where he says that it is " the department under which we consider what is right according to civil usage and equity: this department is regarded by us as the special sphere of the lawyer. "
881
Sed
quod
ipsius
de
his
libris
iudicium
fuerit
,
supra
dixi
.
Sunt
enim
velut
regestae
in
hos
commentarios
,
quos
adolescens
deduxerat
,
scholae
,
et
si
qua
est
in
his
culpa
,
tradentis
est
,
sive
eum
movit
id
,
quod
Hermagoras
prima
in
hoc
loco
posuit
exempla
ex
quaestionibus
iuris
,
sive
quod
Graeci
πραγματικούς
vocant
iuris
interpretes
.
But I have already mentioned what his opinion was about this particular work. The Rhetorica are simply a collection of school-notes on rhetoric which he worked up into this treatise while quite a young man. Such faults as they possess are due to his instructor. In the present instance he may have been influenced by the fact that the first examples given by Hermagoras of this species are drawn from legal questions, or by the fact that the Greeks call interpreters of the law πραγματικοί.
882
Sed
Cicero
quidem
his
pulcherrimos
illos
de
Oratore
substituit
,
ideoque
culpari
,
tanquam
falsa
praecipiat
,
non
potest
.
Nos
ad
Hermagoran
.
Trans
lationem
hic
primus
omnium
tradidit
,
quanquam
semina
eius
quaedam
citra
nomen
ipsum
apud
Aristotelen
reperiuntur
.
But for these early efforts Cicero substituted his splendid de Oratore and therefore cannot be blamed for giving false instruction. I will now return to Hermagoras. He was the first rhetorician to teach that there was a basis concerned with competence, although the elements of this doctrine are found in Aristotle, without however any mention of the name.
883
Legales
autem
quaestiones
has
fecit
,
scripti
et
voluntatis
(
quam
ipse
vocat
κατὰ
ῥητὸν
καὶ
ὑπεξαίρεσιν
,
id
est
dictum
et
exceptionem
,
quorum
prius
ei
cum
omnibus
commune
est
,
exceptionis
nomen
minus
usitatum
) ,
ratiocinativum
,
ambiguitatis
,
legum
contrariarum
.
The legal questions were according to Hermagoras of five kinds. First the letter of the law and its intention; the names which he gives to these are κατὰ ῥητόν and ὑπεξαίρεσις, that is to say the letter of the law and the exceptions thereto: the first of these classes is found in all writers, but the term exception is less in use. The number is completed by the ratiocinative basis and those dealing with ambiguity and contradictory laws.
884
Albutius
eadem
divisione
usus
detrahit
translationem
,
subiiciens
eam
iuridiciali
.
In
legalibus
quoque
quaestionibus
nullum
putat
esse
,
qui
dicatur
ratiocinativus
.
Scio
plura
inventuros
adhuc
,
qui
legere
antiquos
studiosius
volent
,
sed
ne
haec
quoque
excesserint
modum
vereor
.
Albutius adopts this classification, but eliminates competence, including it under the juridical basis. Further he holds that in legal questions there is no ratiocinative basis. I know that those who are prepared to read ancient writers on rhetoric more carefully than I have, will be able to discover yet more on this subject, but I fear that I may have been too lengthy even in saying what I have said.
885
Ipse
me
paulum
in
alia
,
quam
prius
habuerim
,
opinione
nunc
esse
confiteor
.
Et
fortasse
tutissimum
erat
famae
modo
studenti
nihil
ex
eo
mutare
,
quod
multis
annis
non
sensissem
modo
,
verum
etiam
approbassem
.
I must admit that I am now inclined to take a different view from that which I once held. It would perhaps be safer for my reputation if I were to make no modification in views which I not only held for so many years, but of which I expressed my open approbation.
886
Sed
non
sustineo
esse
conscius
mihi
dissimulati
(
in
eo
praesertim
opere
,
quod
ad
bonorum
iuvenum
aliquam
utilitatem
componimus
)
in
ulla
parte
iudicii
mei
.
Nam
et
Hippocrates
,
clarus
arte
medicinae
,
videtur
honestissime
fecisse
,
quod
quosdam
errores
suos
,
ne
posteri
errarent
,
confessus
est
;
et
M
.
Tullius
non
dubitavit
aliquos
iam
editos
libros
aliis
postea
scriptis
ipse
damnare
,
sicut
Catulum
atque
Lucullum
et
hos
ipsos
,
de
quibus
modo
sum
locutus
,
artis
rhetoricae
.
But I cannot bear to be thought guilty of concealment of the truth as regards any portion of my views, more especially in a work designed for the profit of young men of sound disposition. For Hippocrates, the great physician, in my opinion took the most honourable course in acknowledging some of his errors to prevent those who came after from being led astray, while Cicero had no hesitation about condemning some of his earlier works in books which he published later: I refer to his condemnation of his Lucullus and Catulus and the books on rhetoric which I have already mentioned.
887
Etenim
supervacuus
foret
in
studiis
longior
labor
,
si
nihil
liceret
melius
invenire
praeteritis
.
Neque
tamen
quidquam
ex
iis
,
quae
tum
praecepi
,
supervacuum
fuit
;
ad
easdem
enim
particulas
haec
quoque
,
quae
nunc
praecipiam
,
revertentur
;
ita
neminem
didicisse
paeniteat
,
colligere
tantum
eadem
ac
disponere
paulo
significantius
conor
.
Omnibus
autem
satisfactum
volo
,
non
me
hoc
serius
demonstrare
aliis
,
quam
mihi
ipse
persuaserim
.
Indeed we should have no justification for protracting our studies if we were forbidden to improve upon our original views. Still none of my past teaching was superfluous: for the views which I am now going to produce will be found to be based on the same principles, and consequently no one need be sorry to have attended my lectures, since all that I am now attempting to do is to collect and rearrange my original views so that they may be somewhat more instructive. But I wish to satisfy everybody and not to lay myself open to the accusation that I have allowed a long time to elapse between the formation and publication of my views.
888
Secundum
plurimos
auctores
servabam
tris
rationales
status
,
coniecturam
,
qualitatem
,
finitionem
,
unum
legalem
.
Hi
mihi
status
generales
erant
.
Legalem
in
quinque
species
partiebar
,
scripti
et
voluntatis
,
legum
contrariarum
,
collectivum
,
ambiguitatis
,
translationis
.
I used to follow the majority of authorities in adhering to three rational bases, the conjectural, qualitative and definitive, and to one legal basis. These were my general bases. The legal basis I divided into five species, dealing with the letter of the law and intention, contradictory laws, the syllogism, ambiguity and competence.
889
Nunc
quartum
ex
generalibus
intelligo
posse
removeri
;
sufficit
enim
prima
divisio
,
qua
diximus
alios
rationales
,
alios
legales
esse
;
ita
non
erit
status
,
sed
quaestionum
genus
;
alioqui
et
rationalis
status
esset
.
It is now clear to me that the fourth of the general bases may be removed, since the original division which I made into rational and legal bases is sufficient. The fourth therefore will not be a basis, but a kind of question; if it were not, it would form one of the rational bases.
890
Ex
iis
etiam
,
quos
speciales
vocabam
,
removi
translationem
,
frequenter
quidem
(
sicut
omnes
qui
me
secuti
sunt
meminisse
possunt
)
testatus
et
in
ipsis
etiam
illis
sermonibus
me
nolente
vulgatis
hoc
tamen
complexus
,
vix
in
ulla
controversia
translationis
statum
posse
reperiri
,
ut
non
et
alius
in
eadem
recte
dici
videretur
,
ideoque
a
quibusdam
eum
exclusum
.
Further I have removed competence from those which I called species. For I often asserted, as all who have attended my lectures will remember, and even those discourses which were published against my will included the statement, that the basis concerned with competence hardly ever occurs in any dispute under such circumstances that it cannot more correctly be given some other name, and that consequently some rhetoricians exclude it from their list of bases.
891
ferri
,
cum
in
omnibus
fere
causis
,
in
quibus
cecidisse
quis
formula
dicitur
,
hae
sint
quaestiones
,
an
huic
,
an
cum
hoc
,
an
hac
lege
,
an
apud
hunc
,
an
hoc
tempore
liceat
agere
?
I am, however, well aware that the point of competence is raised in many cases, since in practically every case in which a party is said to have been ruled out of court through some error of form, questions such as the following arise: whether it was lawful for this person to bring an action, or to bring it against some particular person, or under a given law, or in such a court, or at such a time, and so on
892
et
si
qua
sunt
talia
.
Sed
personae
,
tempora
,
actiones
ceteraque
propter
aliquam
causam
transferuntur
;
ita
non
est
in
translatione
quaestio
sed
in
eo
,
propter
quod
transferuntur
: "
Non
debes
apud
praetorem
petere
fidei
commissum
,
sed
apud
consules
,
maior
enim
praetoria
cognitione
summa
est
. "
Quaeritur
,
an
maior
summa
sit
,
facti
controversia
est
.
But the question of competence as regards persons, times, legal actions and the rest originates in some pre-existent cause: the question turns therefore not on competence itself, but on the cause with which the point of competence originates. " You ought to demand the return of a deposit not before the praetor but before the consuls, as the sum is too large to come under the praetor's jurisdiction. " The question then arises whether the sum is too large, and the dispute is one
893 "
Non
licet
tibi
agere
mecum
,
cognitor
enim
fieri
non
potuisti
: "
iudicatio
,
an
potuerit
. "
Non
debuisti
interdicere
sed
petere
: "
an
recte
interdictum
sit
,
ambigitur
.
Quae
omnia
succedunt
legitimis
quaestionibus
.
of fact. " You have no right to bring an action against me, as it is impossible for you to have been appointed to represent the actual plaintiff. " It then has to be decided whether he could have been so appointed. " You ought not to have proceeded by interdict, but to have put in a plea for possession. " The point in doubt is whether the interdict is legal. All these points fall under the head of legal questions.
894
An
non
praescriptiones
(
etiam
in
quibus
maxime
videtur
manifesta
translatio
)
easdem
omnes
species
habent
,
quas
eae
leges
,
quibus
agitur
,
ut
aut
de
nomine
aut
scripto
et
sententia
vel
ratiocinatione
quaeratur
?
Deinde
status
ex
quaestione
oritur
;
translatio
non
habet
quaestionem
,
de
qua
contendit
orator
,
sed
propter
quam
contendit
.
not even those special pleas, in which questions of competence make themselves most evident, give rise to the same species of question as those laws under which the action is brought, so that the enquiry is really concerned with the name of a given act, with the letter of the law and its meaning, or with something that requires to be settled by argument? The basis originates from the question, and in cases of competence it is not the question concerning which the advocate argues that is involved, but the question on account of which he argues.
895
Hoc
apertius
, "
Occidisti
hominem
" , "
Non
occidi
; "
quaestio
,
an
occiderit
,
status
coniectura
.
Non
est
tale
, "
Habeo
ius
actionis
" , "
Non
habes
, "
ut
sit
quaestio
,
an
habeat
,
et
inde
status
.
Accipiat
enim
actionem
necne
,
ad
eventum
pertinet
,
non
ad
causam
,
et
ad
id
,
quod
pronuntiat
iudex
,
non
id
,
propter
quod
pronuntiat
.
An example will make this clearer. "You have killed a man. "I did not kill him." The question is whether he has killed him; the basis is the conjectural. But the following case is very different. "I have the right to bring this action. "You have not the right." The question is whether he has the right, and it is from this that we derive the basis. For whether he is allowed the right or not depends on the event, not on the cause itself, and on the decision of the judge, not on that on account of which he gives such a decision.
896
Hoc
illi
simile
est
, "
Puniendus
es
" , "
Non
sum
; "
videbit
iudex
,
an
puniendus
sit
.
Sed
non
hic
erit
quaestio
nec
hic
status
.
Ubi
ergo
? "
Puniendus
es
,
hominem
occidisti
" ; "
Non
occidi
: "
An
occiderit
. "
Honorandus
sum
" , "
Non
es
; "
num
statum
habet
?
non
,
ut
puto
. "
Honorandus
sum
,
quia
tyrannum
occidi
" ; "
Non
occidisti
; "
quaestio
et
status
.
The following is a similar example. "You ought to be punished. "I ought not." The judge will decide whether he should be punished, but it is not with this that the question or the basis is concerned. Where then does the question lie? "You ought to be punished, for you have killed a man. "I did not kill him." The question is whether he killed him. "I ought to receive some honour. "You ought not." Does this involve a basis? I think not. "I ought to receive some honour for killing a tyrant. "You did not kill him." Here there is a question and a basis as well.
897
Similiter
, "
Non
recte
agis
" , "
Recte
ago
"
non
habet
statum
.
Ubi
est
ergo
? "
Non
recte
agis
ignominiosus
. "
Quaeritur
,
an
ignominiosus
sit
;
aut
,
an
agere
ignominioso
liceat
;
quaestiones
et
status
.
Ergo
translativum
genus
causae
ut
comparativum
et
mutuae
accusationis
.
So, too, "You are not entitled to bring this action, "I have," involves no basis. Where then is it to be found? "You have no right to bring this action, because you have been deprived of civil rights." In this case the question is whether he has been so deprived, or whether loss of civil rights debars a person from bringing an action. Here on the other hand we find both questions and bases. It is therefore to kinds of causes, not to bases that the term competence applies: other kinds of cause are the comparative and the recriminatory.
898
At
enim
simile
est
illi
"
Habeo
ius
" , "
Non
habes
, "
Occidisti
" , "
Recte
occidi
. "
Non
nego
,
sed
nec
haec
res
status
facit
.
Non
enim
sunt
hae
propositiones
(
alioqui
causa
non
explicabitur
) ,
sed
,
cum
suis
rationibus
. "
Scelus
commisit
Horatius
,
sororem
enim
occidit
.
Non
commisit
,
debuit
enim
occidere
eam
,
quae
hostis
mortem
maerebat
. "
Quaestio
,
an
haec
iusta
causa
;
ita
qualitas
.
"But," it is urged, " the case 'I have a right,' 'You have not,' is similar to 'You have killed a man,' 'I was justified in so doing.' " I do not deny it, but this does not make it a basis. For these statements are not propositions until the reasons for them are added. If they were propositions as they stand, the case could not proceed. "Horatius has committed a crime, for he has killed his sister. " He has not committed a crime, since it was his duty to kill her for mourning the death of an enemy. " The question is whether this was a justifiable reason, and the basis is one of quality. So too as regards competence.
899
Et
similiter
in
translatione
, "
Non
habes
ius
abdicandi
,
quia
ignominioso
non
est
actio
.
Habeo
ius
,
quia
abdicatio
actio
non
est
. "
Quaeritur
,
quid
sit
actio
:
finiemus
"
Non
licet
abdicare
filium
"
syllogismo
.
Item
cetera
per
omnes
et
rationales
et
legales
status
.
" You have no right to disinherit, since a person who has been deprived of civil rights is not allowed to take legal action. "I have the right, since disinheriting is not legal action." The question here is what is legal action. And we shall arrive at the conclusion that the son's disinheritance is unlawful, by use of the syllogism. The case will be similar with all the rational and legal bases.
900
Nec
ignoro
fuisse
quosdam
,
qui
translationem
in
rationali
quoque
genere
ponerent
hoc
nodo
, "
Hominem
occidi
,
iussus
ab
imperatore
.
Dona
templi
cogenti
tyranno
dedi
.
Deserui
tempestatibus
,
luminibus
,
valetudine
impeditus
. "
Id
est
,
non
per
me
stetit
,
sed
per
illud
.
A
quibus
etiam
liberius
dissentio
.
I am aware that there have been some who placed competence among rational bases, using as illustrations cases such as, "I killed a man under orders from my general, "I gave the votive offerings in a temple to a tyrant under compulsion, " I deserted owing to the fact that storms or floods or ill health prevented me from rejoining. " That is to say it was not due to me, but some external cause.
901
Non
enim
actio
transfertur
sed
causa
facti
,
quod
accidit
paene
in
omni
defensione
.
Deinde
is
,
qui
tali
utitur
patrocinio
,
non
recedit
a
forma
qualitatis
,
dicit
enim
,
se
culpa
vacare
;
ut
magis
qualitatis
duplex
ratio
facienda
sit
,
altera
qua
et
factum
defenditur
,
altera
qua
tantum
reus
.
From these writers I differ even more widely: for it is not the nature of the legal action itself which is involved in the question of competence, but the cause of the act; and this is the case in almost every defence. Finally he who adopts this line of defence, does not thereby abandon the qualitative basis; for he states that he himself is free from blame, so that we really should differentiate between two kinds of quality one of which comes into play when both the accused person and his act are defended, and the other when the accused person alone is defended.
902
Credendum
est
igitur
his
,
quorum
auctoritatem
secutus
est
Cicero
,
tria
esse
,
quae
in
omni
disputatione
quaerantur
,
an
sit
,
quid
sit
,
quale
sit
?
quod
ipsa
nobis
etiam
natura
praescribit
.
Nam
primum
oportet
subesse
aliquid
,
de
quo
ambigitur
;
quod
,
quid
sit
et
quale
sit
,
certe
non
potest
aestimari
,
nisi
prius
esse
constiterit
,
ideoque
ea
prima
quaestio
.
We must therefore accept the view of the authorities followed by Cicero, to the effect that there are three things on which enquiry is made in every case: we ask whether a thing is, that it is, and of that kind it is. Nature herself imposes this upon us. For first of all there must be some subject for the question, since we cannot possibly determine what a thing is, or of what kind it is, until we have first ascertained whether it is, and therefore the first question raised is whether it is. But even when it is clear that a thing is,
903
Sed
non
statim
,
quod
esse
manifestum
est
,
etiam
quid
sit
,
apparet
.
Hoc
quoque
constituto
novissima
qualitas
superest
,
neque
his
exploratis
aliud
est
ultra
.
His
infinitae
quaestiones
,
his
finitae
continentur
;
horum
aliqua
in
demonstrativa
,
deliberativa
,
iudiciali
materia
utique
tractatur
.
it is not immediately obvious what it is. And when we have decided what it is, there remains the question of its quality. These three points once ascertained, there is no further question to ask. These heads cover both definite and indefinite questions. One or more of them is discussed in every demonstrative, deliberative or forensic theme.
904
Haec
rursus
iudiciales
causas
et
rationali
parte
et
legali
continent
;
neque
enim
ulla
iuris
disceptatio
nisi
finitione
,
qualitate
,
coniectura
potest
explicari
.
These heads again cover all cases in the courts, whether we regard them from the point of view of rational or legal questions. For no legal problem can be settled save by the aid of definition, quality and conjecture.
905
Sed
instituentibus
rudes
non
erit
inutilis
latius
primo
fusa
ratio
et
,
si
non
statim
rectissima
linea
tensa
,
facilior
tamen
et
apertior
via
.
Discant
igitur
ante
omnia
quadripertitam
in
omnibus
causis
esse
rationem
,
quam
primam
intueri
debeat
qui
acturus
est
.
Nam
,
ut
a
defensore
potissimum
incipiam
,
longe
fortissima
tuendi
se
ratio
est
,
si
quod
obiicitur
negari
potest
;
proxima
,
si
non
id
,
quod
obiicitur
,
factum
esse
dicitur
;
tertia
honestissima
,
qua
recte
factum
defenditur
.
Quibus
si
deficiamur
,
ultima
quidem
sed
iam
sola
superest
salus
aliquo
iuris
adiutorio
elabendi
ex
crimine
,
quod
neque
negari
neque
defendi
potest
,
ut
non
videatur
iure
actio
intendi
.
Those, however, who are engaged in instructing the ignorant will find it useful at first to adopt a slightly less rigid method: the road will not be absolutely straight to begin with, but it will be more open and will provide easier going. I would have them therefore learn above all things that there are four different methods which may be employed in every case, and he who is going to plead should study them as first essentials. For, to begin with the defendant, far the strongest method of self-defence is, if possible, to deny the charge. The second best is when it is possible to reply that the particular act with which you are charged was never committed. The third and most honourable is to maintain that the act was justifiable. If none of these lines of defence are feasible, there remains the last and only hope of safety: if it is impossible either to deny the charge or justify the act, we must evade the charge with the aid of some point of law, making it appear that the action has been brought against us illegally
906
Hinc
illae
quaestiones
sive
actiones
sive
translationes
.
Sunt
enim
quaedam
non
laudabilia
non
natura
sed
iure
concessa
,
ut
in
XII
tabulis
debitoris
corpus
inter
creditores
dividi
licuit
,
quam
legem
mos
publicus
repudiavit
;
et
aliquid
aequum
sed
prohibitum
iure
,
ut
libertas
testamentorum
.
Hence arise those questions of legal action or competence. For there are some things, which, although not laudable in themselves, are yet permitted by law; witness the passage in the Twelve Tables authorising creditors to divide up a debtor's body amongst themselves, a law which is repudiated by public custom. There are also certain things which although equitable are prohibited by law; witness the restrictions placed on testamentary disposition.
907
Accusatori
nihilo
plura
intuenda
sunt
,
ut
probet
factum
esse
,
hoc
esse
factum
,
non
recte
factum
,
iure
se
intendere
.
Ita
circa
species
easdem
lis
omnis
versabitur
translatis
tantum
aliquando
partibus
,
ut
in
causis
,
quibus
de
praemio
agitur
,
recte
factum
petitor
probat
.
The accuser likewise has four things which he must keep in mind: he must prove that something was done, that a particular act was done, that it was wrongly done, and that he brings his charge according to law. Thus every cause will turn on the same sorts of questions, though the parts of plaintiff and defendant will sometimes be interchanged: for instance in the case of a claim for a reward, it will be the plaintiffs task to show that what was done was right.
908
Haec
quattuor
velut
proposita
formaeque
actionis
,
quae
tum
generales
status
vocabam
,
in
duo
(
ut
ostendi
)
genera
discedunt
rationale
et
legale
.
Rationale
simplicius
est
,
quia
ipsius
tantum
naturae
contemplatione
constat
.
Itaque
in
eo
satis
est
ostendisse
coniecturam
,
finitionem
,
qualitatem
.
These four schemes or forms of action which I then called general bases fall into two classes as I have shown, namely, the rational and the legal. The rational is the simpler, as it involves nothing more than the consideration of the nature of things. In this connection, therefore, a mere mention of conjeclure, definition and quality will suffice.
909
Legalium
plures
sint
species
necesse
est
,
propterea
quod
multae
sunt
leges
et
varias
habent
formas
.
Alia
est
cuius
verbis
nitimur
,
alia
cuius
voluntate
,
alias
nobis
,
cum
ipsi
nullam
habeamus
,
adiungimus
,
alias
inter
se
comparamus
,
alias
in
diversum
interpretamur
.
Legal questions necessarily have a larger number of species, since there are many laws and a variety of forms. In the case of one law we rely on the letter, in others on the spirit. Some laws we force to serve our turn, when we can find no law to support our case, others we compare with one another, and on others we put some novel interpretation.
910
Sic
nascuntur
haec
velut
simulacra
ex
illis
tribus
,
interim
simplicia
,
interim
et
mixta
,
propriam
tamen
faciem
ostendentia
,
ut
scripti
et
voluntatis
,
quae
sine
dubio
aut
qualitate
aut
coniectura
continentur
,
et
syllogismos
,
qui
est
maxime
qualitatis
,
et
leges
contrariae
,
quae
iisdem
,
quibus
scriptum
et
voluntas
,
constant
,
et
ἀμφιβολία
,
quae
semper
coniectura
explicatur
.
Thus from these three bases we get three resemblances of bases: sometimes simple, sometimes complex, but all having a character of their own, as, for instance, when questions of the letter of the law and its intention are involved, for these clearly come under conjecture or quality; or again where the syllogism is involved, for this is specially connected with quality; or where contradictory laws are involved, for these are on the same footing as the letter of the law and intention; or yet again in cases of ambiguity, which is always resolved by conjecture.
911
Finitio
quoque
utrique
generi
,
quodque
rerum
quodque
scripti
contemplatione
constat
,
communis
est
.
Haec
omnia
,
etiamsi
in
illos
tres
status
veniunt
,
tamen
,
quia
(
ut
dixi
)
habent
aliquid
velut
proprium
,
videntur
demonstranda
discentibus
,
et
permittendum
ea
dicere
vel
status
legales
vel
quaestiones
vel
capita
quaedam
minora
,
dum
sciant
,
nihil
ne
in
his
quidem
praeter
tria
,
quae
praediximus
,
quaeri
.
Definition also belongs to both classes of question, namely those concerned with the consideration of facts and those concerned with the letter of the law. All these questions, although they come under the three bases, yet since, as I have mentioned, they have certain characteristic features of their own, require to be pointed out to learners; and we must allow them to be called legal bases or questions or minor heads, as long as it is clearly understood that none of them involve any other questions than the three I have mentioned.
912
At
"
Quantum
? "
et
"
Quam
multum
? "
et
"
Ad
aliquid
"
et
,
ut
nonnulli
putarunt
,
comparativus
non
eandem
rationem
habent
;
sunt
enim
haec
non
ad
varietatem
iuris
sed
ad
solam
rationem
referenda
,
ideoque
semper
in
parte
aut
coniecturae
aut
qualitatis
ponenda
sunt
,
ut
"
Qua
mente
? "
et
"
Quo
tempore
? "
et
"
Quo
loco
? "
As regards questions of quantity, number, relation, and, as some have thought, comparison, the case is different. For these have no connexion with the complexities of the law, but are concerned with reason only. Consequently they must always be regarded as coming under conjecture or quality, as, for instance, when we ask with what purpose, or at what time, or place something was done.