Nominative
Accusative
Dative
Ablative
Genitive
Vocative
Locative
Passive
Deponent
Institutio Oratoria (Quintilian)
Rainbow Latin Reader
[Close]
 

Institutio Oratoria

Author: Quintilian
Translator: Harold Edgeworth Butler
609
Haec
opinio
originem
ab
Isocrate
(
si
tamen
re
vera
Ars
,
quae
circumfertur
,
eius
est
)
duxit
.
Qui
,
cum
longe
sit
a
voluntate
infamantium
oratoris
officia
,
finem
artis
temere
comprehendit
,
dicens
esse
rhetoricen
persuadendi
opificem
,
id
est
πειθοῦς
δημιουργόν
;
neque
enim
mihi
permiserim
eadem
uti
declinatione
,
qua
Ennius
M
.
Cethegum
Suadae
medullam
vocat
.
This view is derived from Isocrates, if indeed the treatise on rhetoric which circulates under his name is really from his hand. He, although far from agreeing with those whose aim is to disparage the duties of an orator, somewhat rashly defined rhetoric as πειθοῦς δημιουργός, the "worker of persuasion" : for I cannot bring myself to use the peculiar derivative which Ennius applies to Marcus Cethegus in the phrase suadae medulla, the "marrow of persuasion."
610
Apud
Platonem
quoque
Gorgias
in
libro
,
qui
nomine
eius
inscriptus
est
,
idem
fere
dicit
;
sed
hanc
Plato
illius
opinionem
vult
accipi
non
suam
.
Cicero
pluribus
locis
scripsit
,
officium
oratoris
esse
dicere
apposite
ad
persuadendum
.
Again Gorgias, in the dialogue of Plato that takes its title from his name, says practically the same thing, but Plato intends it to be taken as the opinion of Gorgias, not as his own. Cicero in more than one passage defined the duty of an orator as "speaking in a persuasive manner."
611
In
rhetoricis
etiam
,
quos
sine
dubio
ipse
non
probat
,
finem
facit
persuadere
.
Verum
et
pecunia
persuadet
et
gratia
et
auctoritas
dicentis
et
dignitas
,
postremo
aspectus
etiam
ipse
sine
voce
,
quo
vel
recordatio
meritorum
cuiusque
vel
facies
aliqua
miserabilis
vel
formae
pulchritudo
sententiam
dictat
.
In his Rhelorica too, a work which it is clear gave him no satisfaction, he makes the end to be persuasion. But many other things have the power of persuasion, such as money, influence, the authority and rank of the speaker, or even some sight unsupported by language, when for instance the place of words is supplied by the memory of some individual's great deeds, by his lamentable appearance or the beauty of his person.
612
Nam
et
Manium
Aquilium
defendens
Antonius
,
cum
scissa
veste
cicatrices
,
quas
is
pro
patria
pectore
adverso
suscepisset
,
ostendit
,
non
orationis
habuit
fiduciam
sed
oculis
populi
Romani
vim
attulit
,
quem
illo
ipso
aspectu
maxime
motum
in
hoc
,
ut
absolveret
reum
,
creditum
est
.
Thus when Antonius in the course of his defence of Manius Aquilius tore open his client's robe and revealed the honourable scars which he had acquired while facing his country's foes, he relied no longer on the power of his eloquence, but appealed directly to the eyes of the Roman people. And it is believed that they were so profoundly moved by the sight as to acquit the accused.
613
Servium
quidem
Galbam
miseratione
sola
,
qua
non
suos
modo
liberos
parvulos
in
contione
produxerat
,
sed
Galli
etiam
Sulpicii
filium
suis
ipse
manibus
circumtulerat
,
elapsum
esse
,
cum
aliorum
monumentis
tum
Catonis
oratione
testatum
est
.
Again there is a speech of Cato, to mention no other records, which informs us that Servius Galba escaped condemnation solely by the pity which he aroused not only by producing his own young children before the assembly, but by carrying round in his arms the son of Sulpicius Gallus.
614
Et
Phrynen
non
Hyperidis
actione
,
quanquam
admirabili
,
sed
conspectu
corporis
,
quod
illa
speciosissimum
alioqui
diducta
nudaverat
tunica
,
putant
periculo
liberatam
.
Quae
si
omnia
persuadent
,
non
est
hic
,
de
quo
locuti
sumus
,
idoneus
finis
.
So also according to general opinion Phryne was saved not by the eloquence of Hyperides, admirable as it was, but by the sight of her exquisite body, which she further revealed by drawing aside her tunic. And if all these have power to persuade, the end of oratory, which we are discussing, cannot adequately be defined as persuasion.
615
Ideoque
diligentiores
sibi
sunt
visi
,
qui
,
cum
de
rhetorice
idem
sentirent
,
existimaverunt
eam
vim
dicendo
persuadendi
.
Quem
finem
Gorgias
in
eodem
,
de
quo
supra
diximus
,
libro
,
velut
coactus
a
Socrate
facit
;
a
quo
non
dissentit
Theodectes
,
sive
ipsius
id
opus
est
,
quod
de
rhetorice
nomine
eius
inscribitur
,
sive
,
ut
creditum
est
,
Aristotelis
,
in
quo
est
,
finem
esse
rhetorices
ducere
homines
dicendo
in
id
,
quod
actor
velit
.
Consequently those who, although holding the same general view of rhetoric, have regarded it as the power of persuasion by speaking, pride themselves on their greater exactness of language. This definition is given by Gorgias, in the dialogue mentioned above, under compulsion from the inexorable logic of Socrates. Theodectes agrees with him, whether the treatise on rhetoric which has come down to us under his name is really by him or, as is generally believed, by Aristotle. In that work the end of rhetoric is defined as the leading of men by the power of speech to the conclusion desired by the orator.
616
Sed
ne
hoc
quidem
satis
est
comprehensum
;
persuadent
enim
dicendo
vel
ducunt
in
id
quod
volunt
alii
quoque
,
ut
meretrices
,
adulatores
,
corruptores
.
At
contra
non
persuadet
semper
orator
;
ut
interim
non
sit
proprius
hic
finis
eius
,
interim
sit
communis
cum
iis
,
qui
ab
oratore
procul
absunt
.
But even this definition is not sufficiently comprehensive, since others besides orators persuade by speaking or lead others to the conclusion desired, as for example harlots, flatterers and seducers. On the other hand the orator is not always engaged on persuasion, so that sometimes persuasion is not his special object, while sometimes it is shared by others who are far removed from being orators.
617
Atqui
non
multum
ab
hoc
fine
abest
Apollodorus
,
dicens
iudicialis
orationis
primum
et
super
omnia
esse
persuadere
iudici
et
sententiam
eius
ducere
in
id
,
quod
velit
;
nam
et
ipse
oratorem
fortunae
subiicit
,
ut
,
si
non
persuaserit
,
nomen
suum
retinere
non
possit
.
And yet Apollodorus is not very far off this definition when he asserts that the first and all-important task of forensic oratory is to persuade the judge and lead his mind to the conclusions desired by the speaker. For even Apollodorus makes the orator the sport of fortune by refusing him leave to retain his title if he fails to persuade.
618
Quidam
recesserunt
ab
eventu
,
sicut
Aristoteles
dicit
:
rhetorice
est
vis
inveniendi
omnia
in
oratione
persuasibilia
.
Qui
finis
et
illud
vitium
,
de
quo
supra
diximus
,
habet
et
insuper
quod
nihil
nisi
inventionem
complectitur
,
quae
sine
elocutione
non
est
oratio
.
Some on the other hand pay no attention to results, as for example Aristotle, who says "rhetoric is the power of discovering all means of persuading by speech." This definition has not merely the fault already mentioned, but the additional defect of including merely the power of invention, which without style cannot possibly constitute oratory.
619
Hermagorae
,
qui
finem
eius
esse
ait
persuasibiliter
dicere
,
et
aliis
,
qui
eandem
sententiam
non
iisdem
tantum
verbis
explicant
ac
finem
esse
demonstrant
dicere
quae
oporteat
omnia
ad
persuadendum
,
satis
responsum
est
,
cum
persuadere
non
tantum
oratoris
esse
convicimus
.
Hermagoras, who asserts that its end is to speak persuasively, and others who express the same opinion, though in different words, and inform us that the end is to say everything which ought to be said with a view to persuasion, have been sufficiently answered above, when I proved that persuasion was not the privilege of the orator alone.
620
Addita
sunt
his
alia
varie
.
Quidam
enim
circa
res
omnes
,
quidam
circa
civiles
modo
versari
rhetoricen
putaverunt
;
quorum
verius
utrum
sit
,
in
eo
loco
,
qui
huius
quaestionis
proprius
est
,
dicam
.
Various additions have been made to these definitions. For some hold that rhetoric is concerned with everything, while some restrict its activity to politics. The question as to which of these views is the nearer to the truth shall be discussed later in its appropriate place.
621
Omnia
subiecisse
oratori
videtur
Aristoteles
,
cum
dixit
vim
esse
videndi
,
quid
in
quaque
re
possit
esse
persuasibile
.
Et
Patrocles
,
qui
non
quidem
adiicit
in
quaque
re
,
sed
nihil
excipiendo
idem
ostendit
;
vim
enim
vocat
inveniendi
,
quod
sit
in
oratione
persuasibile
;
qui
fines
et
ipsi
solam
complectuntur
inventionem
.
Quod
vitium
fugiens
Theodorus
vim
putat
inveniendi
et
eloquendi
cum
ornatu
credibilia
in
omni
oratione
.
Aristotle seems to have implied that the sphere of the orator was all-inclusive when he defined rhetoric as the power to detect every element in any given subject which might conduce to persuasion; so too does Patrocles who omits the words in any given subject, but since he excludes nothing, shows that his view is identical. For he defines rhetoric as the power to discover whatever is persuasive in speech. These definitions like that quoted above include no more than the power of invention alone. Theodorus avoids this fault and holds that it is the power to discover and to utter forth in elegant language whatever is credible in every subject of oratory.
622
Sed
cum
eodem
modo
credibilia
quo
persuasibilia
etiam
non
orator
inveniat
,
adiiciendo
in
omni
oratione
magis
quam
superiores
concedit
scelera
quoque
suadentibus
pulcherrimae
rei
nomen
.
But, while others besides orators may discover what is credible as well as persuasive, by adding the words in every subject he, to a greater extent than the others, concedes the fairest name in all the world to those who use their gifts as an incitement to crime
623
Gorgias
apud
Platonem
suadendi
se
artificem
in
iudiciis
et
aliis
coetibus
esse
ait
,
de
iustis
quoque
et
iniustis
tractare
;
cui
Socrates
persuadendi
,
non
docendi
concedit
facultatem
.
. Plato makes Gorgias say that he is a master of persuasion in the law-courts and other assemblies, and that his themes are justice and injustice, while in reply Socrates allows him the power of persuading, but not of teaching.
624
Qui
vero
non
omnia
subiiciebant
oratori
,
sollicitius
ac
verbosius
,
ut
necesse
erat
,
adhibuerunt
discrimina
;
quorum
fuit
Ariston
,
Critolai
Peripatetici
discipulus
,
cuius
hic
finis
est
,
scientia
videndi
et
agendi
in
quaestionibus
civilibus
per
orationem
popularis
persuasionis
.
Hic
scientiam
,
Those who refused to make the sphere of oratory allinclusive, have been obliged to make somewhat forced and long-winded distinctions: among these I may mention Ariston, the pupil of the Peripatetic Critolaus, who produced the following definition, " Rhetoric is the science of seeing and uttering what ought to be said on political questions in language that is likely to prove persuasive to the people. "
625
quia
Peripateticus
est
,
non
,
ut
Stoici
,
virtutis
loco
ponit
;
popularem
autem
comprehendendo
persuasionem
etiam
contumeliosus
est
adversus
artem
orandi
,
quam
nihil
putat
doctis
persuasuram
.
Illud
de
omnibus
,
qui
circa
civiles
demum
quaestiones
oratorem
iudicant
versari
,
dictum
sit
,
excludi
ab
his
plurima
oratoris
officia
,
illam
certe
laudativam
totam
,
quae
est
rhetorices
pars
tertia
.
Being a Peripatetic he regards it as a science, not, like the Stoics, as a virtue, while in adding the words "likely to prove persuasie to the people" he inflicts a positive insult on oratory, in implying that it is not likely to persuade the learned. The same criticism will apply to all those who restrict oratory to political questions, for they exclude thereby a large number of the duties of an orator, as for example panegyric, the third department of oratory, which is entirely ignored.
626
Cautius
Theodorus
Gadareus
,
ut
iam
ad
eos
veniamus
,
qui
artem
quidem
esse
eam
sed
non
virtutem
putaverunt
.
Ita
enim
dicit
(
ut
ipsis
eorum
verbis
utar
,
qui
haec
ex
Graeco
transtulerunt
) ,
Ars
inventrix
et
iudicatrix
et
enuntiatrix
decenti
ornatu
secundum
mensionem
eius
,
quod
in
quoque
potest
sumi
persuasibile
,
in
materia
civili
.
Turning to those who regard rhetoric as an art, but not as a virtue, we find that Theodorus of Gadara is more cautious. For he says (I quote the words of his translators), " rhetoric is the art which discovers and judges and expresses, mith an elegance duly proportioned to the importance of all such elements of persuasion as may exist in any subject in the field of politics. "
627
Itemque
Cornelius
Celsus
,
qui
finem
rhetorices
ait
dicere
persuasibiliter
in
dubia
civili
materia
.
Quibus
sunt
non
dissimiles
,
qui
ab
aliis
traduntur
;
qualis
est
ille
,
Vis
videndi
et
eloquendi
de
rebus
civilibus
subiectis
sibi
cum
quadam
persuasione
et
quodam
corporis
habitu
et
eorum
,
quae
dicet
,
pronuntiatione
.
Similarly Cornelius Celsus defines the end of rhetoric as to speak persuasively on any doubtful subject within the field of politics. Similar definitions are given by others, such for instance as the following:— " rhetoric is the power of judging and holding forth on such political subjects as come before it with a certain persuasiveness, a certain action of the body and delivery of the words. "
628
Mille
alia
,
sed
aut
eadem
aut
ex
eisdem
composita
;
quibus
item
,
cum
de
materia
rhetorices
dicendum
erit
,
respondebimus
.
Quidam
eam
neque
vim
neque
scientiam
neque
artem
putaverunt
,
sed
Critolaus
usum
dicendi
(
nam
hoc
τριβή
significat
) ,
Athenaeus
fallendi
artem
.
There are countless other definitions, either identical with this or composed of the same elements, which I shall deal with when I come to the questions concerned with the subject matter of rhetoric. Some regard it as neither a power, a science or an art; Critolaus calls it the practice of speaking (for this is the meaning of τριβή ), Athenaeus styles it the art of deceiving,
629
Plerique
autem
,
dum
pauca
ex
Gorgia
Platonis
a
prioribus
imperite
excerpta
legere
contenti
neque
hoc
totum
neque
alia
eius
volumina
evolvunt
,
in
maximum
errorem
inciderunt
,
creduntque
eum
in
hac
esse
opinione
,
ut
rhetoricen
non
artem
sed
peritiam
quandam
gratiae
ac
voluptatis
existimet
;
while the majority, content with reading a few passages from the Gorgias of Plato, unskilfully excerpted by earlier writers, refrain from studying that dialogue and the remainder of Plato's writings, and thereby fall into serious error. For they believe that in Plato's view rhetoric was not an art, but a certain adroitness in the production of delight and gratification,
630
et
alio
loco
civilitatis
particulae
simulacrum
et
quartam
partem
adulationis
,
quod
duas
partes
civilitatis
corpori
adsignet
,
medicinam
et
quam
interpretantur
exercitatricem
,
duas
animo
,
legalem
atque
iustitiam
;
adulationem
autem
medicinae
vocet
cocorum
artificium
,
exercitatricis
mangonum
,
qui
colorem
fuco
et
verum
robur
inani
sagina
mentiantur
,
legalis
cavillatricem
,
iustitiae
rhetoricen
.
or with reference to another passage the shadow of a small part of politics and the fourth department of flattery. For Plato assigns two departments of politics to the body, namely medicine and gymnastic, and two to the soul, namely law and justice, while he styles the art of cookery a form of flattery of medicine, the art of the slave-dealer a flattery of gymnastic, for they produce a false complexion by the use of paint and a false robustness by puffing them out with fat: sophistry he calls a dishonest counterfeit of legal science, and rhetoric of justice.
631
Quae
omnia
sunt
quidem
scripta
in
hoc
libro
dictaque
a
Socrate
,
cuius
persona
videtur
Plato
significare
quid
sentiat
;
sed
alii
sunt
eius
sermones
ad
coarguendos
,
qui
contra
disputant
,
compositi
,
quos
ἐλεγκτικούς
vocant
,
alii
ad
praecipiendum
,
qui
δογματικοί
appellantur
.
All these statements occur in the Gorgias and are uttered by Socrates who appears to be the mouthpiece of the views held by Plato. But some of his dialogues were composed merely to refute his opponents and are styled refutative, while others are for the purpose of teaching and are called doctrinal.
632
Socrates
autem
seu
Plato
eam
quidem
,
quae
tum
exercebatur
,
rhetoricen
talem
putat
,
nam
et
dicit
his
verbis
τοῦτον
τὸν
τρόπον
,
ὃν
ὑμεῖς
πολιτεύεσθε
,
veram
autem
et
honestam
intelligit
.
Itaque
disputatio
ilia
contra
Gorgian
ita
clauditur
,
οὐκοῦν
ἀνάγκη
τὸν
ῥητορικὸν
δίκαιον
εἶναι
,
τὸν
δὲ
δίκαιον
βούλεσθαι
δίκαια
πράττειν
;
Now it is only rhetoric as practised in their own day that is condemned by Plato or Socrates, for he speaks of it as "the manner in which you engage in public affairs" : rhetoric in itself he regards as a genuine and honourable thing, and consequently the controversy with Gorgias ends with the words, "The rhetorician therefore must be just and the just man desirous to do what is just."
633
Ad
quod
ille
quidem
conticescit
,
sed
sermonem
suscipit
Polus
iuvenili
calore
inconsideratior
,
contra
quem
illa
de
simulacro
et
adulatione
dicuntur
.
Tum
Callicles
adhuc
concitatior
,
qui
tamen
ad
hanc
perducitur
clausulam
,
τὸν
μέλλοντα
ὀρθῶς
ῥητορικὸν
ἔσεσθαι
,
δίκαιον
ἄνδρα
δεῖ
εἶναι
καὶ
ἐπιστήμονα
τῶν
δικαίων
;
ut
appareat
,
Platoni
non
rhetoricen
videri
malum
,
sed
eam
veram
nisi
iusto
ac
bono
non
contingere
.
To this Gorgias makes no reply, but the argument is taken up by Polus, a hot-headed and headstrong young fellow, and it is to him that Socrates makes his remarks about "shadows" and "forms of flattery." Then Callicles, who is even more hot-headed, intervenes, but is reduced to the conclusion that "he who would truly be a rhetorician ought to be just and possess a knowledge of justice." It is clear therefore that Plato does not regard rhetoric as an evil, but holds that true rhetoric is impossible for any save a just and good man. In the Phaedrus
634
Adhuc
autem
in
Phaedro
manifestius
facit
,
hanc
artem
consummari
citra
iustitiae
quoque
scientiam
non
posse
;
cui
opinioni
nos
quoque
accedimus
.
An
aliter
defensionem
Socratis
et
eorum
,
qui
pro
patria
ceciderant
,
laudem
scripsisset
?
he makes it even clearer that the complete attainment of this art is impossible without the knowledge of justice, an opinion in which I heartily concur. Had this not been his view, would he have ever written the Apology of Socrates or the Funeral Oration in praise of those who had died in battle for their country, both of them works falling within the sphere of oratory.
635
quae
certe
sunt
oratoris
opera
.
Sed
in
illud
hominum
genus
,
quod
facilitate
dicendi
male
utebatur
,
invectus
est
.
Nam
et
Socrates
inhonestam
sibi
credidit
orationem
,
quam
ei
Lysias
reo
composuerat
;
et
tum
maxime
scribere
litigatoribus
,
quae
illi
pro
se
ipsi
dicerent
,
erat
moris
,
atque
ita
iuri
,
quo
non
licebat
pro
altero
agere
,
fraus
adhibebatur
.
It was against the class of men who employed their glibness of speech for evil purposes that he directed his denunciations. Similarly Socrates thought it incompatible with his honour to make use of the speech which Lysias composed for his defence, although it was the usual practice in those days to write speeches for the parties concerned to speak in the courts on their own behalf, a device designed to circumvent the law which forbade the employment of advocates.
636
Doctores
quoque
eius
artis
parum
idonei
Platoni
videbantur
,
qui
rhetoricen
a
iustitia
separarent
et
veris
credibilia
praeferrent
;
nam
id
quoque
dicit
in
Phaedro
.
Further the teachers of rhetoric were regarded by Plato as quite unsuited to their professed task. For they divorced rhetoric from justice and preferred plausibility to truth, as he states in the Phaedrus.
637
Consensisse
autem
illis
superioribus
videri
potest
etiam
Cornelius
Celsus
,
cuius
haec
verba
sunt
:
Orator
simile
tantum
veri
petit
.
Deinde
paulo
post
:
Non
enim
bona
conscientia
sed
victoria
litigantis
est
praemium
.
Quae
si
vera
essent
,
pessimorum
hominum
foret
,
haec
tam
perniciosa
nocentissimis
moribus
dare
instrumenta
et
nequitiam
praeceptis
adiuvare
.
Sed
illi
rationem
opinionis
suae
viderint
.
Cornelius Celsus seems to have agreed with these early rhetoricians, for he writes "The orator only aims at the semblance of truth," and again a little later "The reward of the party to a suit is not a good conscience, but victory." If this were true, only the worst of men would place such dangerous weapons at the disposal of criminals or employ the precepts of their art for the assistance of wickedness. However I will leave those who maintain these views to consider what ground they have for so doing.
638
Nos
autem
ingressi
formare
perfectum
oratorem
,
quem
in
primis
esse
virum
bonum
volumus
,
ad
eos
qui
de
hoc
opere
melius
sentiunt
,
revertamur
.
Rhetoricen
autem
quidam
eandem
civilitatem
esse
iudicaverunt
;
Cicero
scientiae
civilis
partem
vocat
(
civilis
autem
scientia
idem
quod
sapientia
est
) ;
quidam
eandem
philosophiam
,
For my part, I have undertaken the task of moulding the ideal orator, and as my first desire is that he should be a good man, I will return to those who have sounder opinions on the subject. Some however identify rhetoric with politics, Cicero calls it a department of the science of politics (and science of politics and philosophy are identical terms), while others again call it a branch of philosophy, among them Isocrates.
639
quorum
est
Isocrates
.
Huic
eius
substantiae
maxime
conveniet
finitio
,
rhetoricen
esse
bene
dicendi
scientiam
.
Nam
et
orationis
omnes
virtutes
semel
complectitur
et
protinus
etiam
mores
oratoris
,
cum
bene
dicere
non
possit
nisi
bonus
.
The definition which best suits its real character is that which makes rhetoric the science of speaking well. For this definition includes all the virtues of oratory and the character of the orator as well, since no man can speak well who is not good himself.
640
Idem
valet
Chrysippi
finis
ille
ductus
a
Cleanthe
scientia
recte
dicendi
.
Sunt
plures
eiusdem
,
sed
ad
alias
quaestiones
magis
pertinent
.
Idem
sentit
et
finis
hoc
modo
comprehensus
,
persuadere
quod
oporteat
,
nisi
quod
artem
ad
exitum
alligat
.
The definition given by Chrysippus, who derived it from Cleanthes, to the effect that it is the science of speaking rightly, amounts to the same thing. The same philosopher also gives other definitions, but they concern problems of a different character from that on which we are now engaged. Another definition defines oratory as the power of persuading men to do what ought to be done, and yields practically the same sense save that it limits the art to the result which it produces.
641
At
bene
Areus
dicere
secundum
virtutem
orationis
.
Excludunt
a
rhetorice
malos
et
illi
,
qui
scientiam
civilium
officiorum
eam
putaverunt
,
si
scientiam
virtutem
iudicant
;
sed
anguste
intra
civiles
quaestiones
coercent
.
Albucius
,
non
obscurus
professor
atque
auctor
,
scientiam
bene
dicendi
esse
consentit
,
sed
exceptionibus
peccat
adiiciendo
circa
civiles
quaestiones
et
credibiliter
;
quarum
utrique
iam
responsum
est
.
Areus again defines it well as speaking according to the excellence of speech. Those who regard it as the science of political obligations, also exclude men of bad character from the title of orator, if by science they mean virtue, but restrict it overmuch by confining it to political problems. Albutius, a distinguished author and professor of rhetoric, agrees that rhetoric is the science of speaking well, but makes a mistake in imposing restrictions by the addition of the words on political questions and with credibility; with both of these restrictions I have already dealt.
642
Probabilis
et
illi
voluntatis
,
qui
recte
sentire
et
dicere
rhetorices
putaverunt
.
Hi
sunt
fere
fines
maxime
illustres
et
de
quibus
praecipue
disputatur
.
Nam
omnes
quidem
persequi
neque
attinet
neque
possum
,
cum
pravum
quoddam
,
ut
arbitror
,
studium
circa
scriptores
artium
extiterit
,
nihil
eisdem
verbis
,
quae
prior
aliquis
occupasset
,
finiendi
,
quae
ambitio
procul
aberit
a
me
.
Finally those critics who hold that the aim of rhetoric is to think and speak rightly, were on the correct track. These are practically all the most celebrated and most discussed definitions of rhetoric. It would be both irrelevant and beyond my power to deal with all. For I strongly disapprove of the custom which has come to prevail among writers of text-books of refusing to define anything in the same terms as have been employed by some previous writer. I will have nothing to do with such ostentation.
643
Dicam
enim
non
utique
quae
invenero
sed
quae
placebunt
,
sicut
hoc
,
rhetoricen
esse
bene
dicendi
scientiam
;
cum
reperto
quod
est
optimum
,
qui
quaerit
aliud
,
peius
velit
.
His
approbatis
,
simul
manifestum
est
illud
quoque
,
quem
finem
vel
quid
summum
et
ultimum
habeat
rhetorice
,
quod
τέλος
dicitur
,
ad
quod
omnis
ars
tendit
;
nam
si
est
ipsa
bene
dicendi
scientia
,
finis
eius
et
summum
est
bene
dicere
.
What I say will not necessarily be my own invention, but it will be what I believe to be the right view, as for instance that oratory is the science of speaking well. For when the most satisfactory definition has been found, he who seeks another, is merely looking for a worse one. Thus much being admitted we are now in a position to see clearly what is the end, the highest aim, the ultimate goal of rhetoric, that τέλος in fact which every art must possess. For if rhetoric is the science of speaking well, its end and highest aim is to speak well.
644
Sequitur
quaestio
,
an
utilis
rhetorice
.
Nam
quidam
vehementer
in
eam
invehi
solent
,
et
,
quod
sit
indignissimum
,
in
accusationem
orationis
utuntur
orandi
viribus
:
There follows the question as to whether rhetoric is useful. Some are in the habit of denouncing it most violently and of shamelessly employing the powers of oratory to accuse oratory itself.
645
eloquentiam
esse
,
quae
poenis
eripiat
scelestos
,
cuius
fraude
damnentur
interim
boni
,
consilia
ducantur
in
peius
,
nec
seditiones
modo
turbaeque
populares
sed
bella
etiam
inexpiabilia
excitentur
;
cuius
denique
tum
maximus
sit
usus
,
cum
pro
falsis
contra
veritatem
valet
.
"It is eloquence" they say " that snatches criminals from the penalties of the law, eloquence that from time to time secures the condemnation of the innocent and leads deliberation astray, eloquence that stirs up not merely sedition and popular tumult, but wars beyond all expiation, and that is most effective when it makes falsehood prevail over the truth. "
646
Nam
et
Socrati
obiiciunt
comici
docere
eum
,
quomodo
peiorem
causam
meliorem
faciat
,
et
contra
Tisian
et
Gorgian
similia
dicit
polliceri
Plato
.
The comic poets even accuse Socrates of teaching how to make the worse cause seem the better, while Plato says that Gorgias and Tisias made similar professions.